module Cat.Functor.Hom.Representable {o κ} {C : Precategory o κ} where
private module C = Cat.Reasoning C module C^ = Cat.Reasoning Cat[ C ^op , Sets κ ] module [C,Sets] = Cat.Reasoning Cat[ C , Sets κ ] module Sets = Cat.Reasoning (Sets κ) open Element-hom open Functor open Element open _=>_
Representable functors🔗
A functor (from a locally category) is said to be representable when it is naturally isomorphic to for an object (called the representing object) — that is, the functor classifies the maps into Note that we can evidently dualise the definition, to get what is called a corepresentable functor, one of the form but we refer informally to both of these situations as “representables” and “representing objects”.
record Representation (F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)) : Type (o ⊔ κ) where no-eta-equality field rep : C.Ob represents : F ≅ⁿ Hom-into C rep module rep = Isoⁿ represents equiv : ∀ {a} → C.Hom a rep ≃ F ʻ a equiv = Equiv.inverse (natural-iso→equiv represents _) module Rep {a} = Equiv (equiv {a}) open Representation open Representation using (module Rep) public
This definition is deceptively simple: the idea of representable functor (and of representing object) is key to understanding the idea of universal property, which could be called the most important concept in category theory. Most constructions in category theory specified in terms of the existence of certain maps are really instances of representing objects for functors: limits, colimits, coends, adjoint functors, Kan extensions, etc.
The first thing we will observe is an immediate consequence of the Yoneda lemma: representing objects are unique. Intuitively this is because “ is a representation of ” determines how reacts to being mapped into, and since the only thing we can probe objects in an arbitrary category by are morphisms, two objects which react to morphisms in the same way must be isomorphic.
representation-unique : {F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)} (X Y : Representation F) → X .rep C.≅ Y .rep representation-unique X Y = is-ff→essentially-injective {F = よ C} (よ-is-fully-faithful C) よX≅よY where よX≅よY : よ₀ C (X .rep) C^.≅ よ₀ C (Y .rep) よX≅よY = Y .represents C^.∘Iso X .represents C^.Iso⁻¹
Therefore, if is a univalent category, then the type of representations for a functor is a proposition. This does not follow immediately from the lemma above: we also need to show that the isomorphism computed by the full-faithfulness of the Yoneda embedding commutes with the specified representation isomorphism. This follows by construction, but the proof needs to commute applications of functors and paths-from-isos, which is never pretty:
Representation-is-prop : ∀ {F} → is-category C → is-prop (Representation F) Representation-is-prop {F = F} c-cat x y = path where module X = Representation x module Y = Representation y objs : X.rep ≡ Y.rep objs = c-cat .to-path (representation-unique x y) path : x ≡ y path i .rep = objs i path i .represents = C^.≅-pathp refl (ap (よ₀ C) objs) {f = X.represents} {g = Y.represents} (Nat-pathp _ _ λ a → Hom-pathp-reflr (Sets _) {A = F .F₀ a} {q = λ i → el! (C.Hom a (objs i))} (funext λ x → ap (λ e → e .Sets.to) (ap-F₀-iso (Hom-from C a) c-cat _) $ₚ _ ·· sym (Y.rep.to .is-natural _ _ _) $ₚ _ ·· ap Y.Rep.from (sym (X.rep.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _) ·· ap X.Rep.to (C.idl _) ·· X.Rep.ε _))) i
As terminal objects🔗
We begin to connect the idea of representing objects to other universal constructions by proving this alternative characterisation of representations: A functor is representable if, and only if, its category of elements has a terminal object.
terminal-element→representation : {F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)} → Terminal (∫ C F) → Representation F terminal-element→representation {F} term = f-rep where module F = Functor F open Terminal term
From the terminal object in 1, we obtain a natural transformation given componentwise by interpreting each pair as an object of then taking the terminating morphism which satisfies (by definition) This natural transformation is componentwise invertible, as the calculation below shows, so it constitutes a natural isomorphism.
nat : F => よ₀ C (top .ob) nat .η ob section = has⊤ (elem ob section) .centre .hom nat .is-natural x y f = funext λ sect → ap hom $ has⊤ _ .paths $ elem-hom _ $ F.₁ (has⊤ _ .centre .hom C.∘ f) (top .section) ≡⟨ happly (F.F-∘ _ _) _ ⟩≡ F.₁ f (F.₁ (has⊤ _ .centre .hom) (top .section)) ≡⟨ ap (F.₁ f) (has⊤ _ .centre .commute) ⟩≡ F.₁ f sect ∎ inv : ∀ x → Sets.is-invertible (nat .η x) inv x = Sets.make-invertible (λ f → F.₁ f (top .section)) (funext λ x → ap hom $ has⊤ _ .paths (elem-hom x refl)) (funext λ x → has⊤ _ .centre .commute) f-rep : Representation F f-rep .rep = top .ob f-rep .represents = C^.invertible→iso nat $ invertible→invertibleⁿ nat inv
In the other direction, we take the terminal element to be the image of the identity on the representing object.
representation→terminal-element : {F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)} → Representation F → Terminal (∫ C F) representation→terminal-element {F} F-rep = term where module F = Functor F module R = rep F-rep open Terminal term : Terminal (∫ C F) term .top .ob = F-rep .rep term .top .section = R.from .η _ C.id term .has⊤ (elem o s) .centre .hom = R.to .η _ s term .has⊤ (elem o s) .centre .commute = F.₁ (R.to .η o s) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡˘⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩≡˘ R.from .η _ ⌜ C.id C.∘ R.to .η o s ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (C.idl _) ⟩≡ R.from .η _ (R.to .η o s) ≡⟨ unext R.invr o s ⟩≡ s ∎ term .has⊤ (elem o s) .paths h = ext $ R.to .η o ⌜ s ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ comm ⟩≡˘ R.to .η o (R.from .η _ (h .hom)) ≡⟨ unext R.invl o _ ⟩≡ h .hom ∎ where comm = R.from .η _ ⌜ h .hom ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ (C.idl _) ⟩≡˘ R.from .η _ (C.id C.∘ h .hom) ≡⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩≡ F.₁ (h .hom) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡⟨ h .commute ⟩≡ s ∎
Universal constructions🔗
In particular, we can show that terminal objects are representing objects for a particular functor. Consider, to be more specific, the constant functor which sends everything to the terminal set. When is representable?
Well, unfolding the definition, it’s when we have an object with a natural isomorphism Unfolding that, it’s an object for which, given any other object we have an isomorphism of sets 2. Hence, a representing object for the “constantly ” functor is precisely a terminal object.
representable-unit→terminal : Representation (Const (el (Lift _ ⊤) (hlevel 2))) → Terminal C representable-unit→terminal repr .Terminal.top = repr .rep representable-unit→terminal repr .Terminal.has⊤ ob = retract→is-contr (Rep.from repr) (λ _ → lift tt) (Rep.η repr) (hlevel 0)
This can be seen as a special case of the construction above: is representable just when its category of elements has a terminal object, but in this case the category of elements of is just
Corepresentable functors🔗
As noted earlier, we can dualise the definition of a representable functor to the covariant setting to get corepresentable functors.
record Corepresentation (F : Functor C (Sets κ)) : Type (o ⊔ κ) where no-eta-equality field corep : C.Ob corepresents : F ≅ⁿ Hom-from C corep module corep = Isoⁿ corepresents coequiv : ∀ {a} → C.Hom corep a ≃ F ʻ a coequiv = Equiv.inverse (natural-iso→equiv corepresents _) module Corep {a} = Equiv (coequiv {a}) open Corepresentation open Corepresentation using (module Corep) public
Much like their contravariant cousins, corepresenting objects are unique up to isomorphism.
corepresentation-unique : {F : Functor C (Sets κ)} (X Y : Corepresentation F) → X .corep C.≅ Y .corep
We omit the proof, as it is identical to the representable case.
corepresentation-unique X Y = is-ff→essentially-injective {F = Functor.op (よcov C)} (よcov-is-fully-faithful C) (iso→co-iso (Cat[ C , Sets κ ]) ni) where ni : Hom-from C (Y .corep) ≅ⁿ Hom-from C (X .corep) ni = X .corepresents ∘ni Y .corepresents ni⁻¹
This implies that the type of corepresentations is a proposition when is univalent.
Corepresentation-is-prop : ∀ {F} → is-category C → is-prop (Corepresentation F)
We opt to not show the proof, as it is even nastier than the proof for representables due to the fact that the yoneda embedding for covariant functors is itself contravariant.
Corepresentation-is-prop {F = F} c-cat X Y = path where objs : X .corep ≡ Y .corep objs = c-cat .to-path (corepresentation-unique X Y) path : X ≡ Y path i .corep = objs i path i .corepresents = [C,Sets].≅-pathp refl (ap (Hom-from C) objs) {f = X .corepresents} {g = Y .corepresents} (Nat-pathp _ _ λ a → Hom-pathp-reflr (Sets _) {A = F .F₀ a} {q = λ i → el! (C.Hom (objs i) a)} (funext λ x → ap (λ e → e .Sets.to) (ap-F₀-iso (Hom-into C a) (opposite-is-category c-cat) _) $ₚ _ ·· sym (corep.to Y .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _) ·· ap (Corep.from Y) (sym (corep.from X .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _) ·· ap (Corep.to X) (C.idr _) ·· Corep.ε X _))) i
Dualising the representable case, we have that a functor is corepresentable if and only if its covariant category of elements has an initial object.
initial-element→corepresentation : {F : Functor C (Sets κ)} → Initial (Co.∫ F) → Corepresentation F corepresentation→initial-element : {F : Functor C (Sets κ)} → Corepresentation F → Initial (Co.∫ F)
The proofs are again entirely analogous to the representable case.
initial-element→corepresentation {F} init = f-corep where module F = Functor F open Initial init open Co.Element open Co.Element-hom nat : F => Hom-from C (bot .ob) nat .η ob section = has⊥ (Co.elem ob section) .centre .hom nat .is-natural x y f = funext λ sect → ap hom $ has⊥ _ .paths $ Co.elem-hom _ $ F.₁ (f C.∘ has⊥ _ .centre .hom) (bot .section) ≡⟨ happly (F.F-∘ _ _) _ ⟩≡ F.₁ f (F.₁ (has⊥ _ .centre .hom) (bot .section)) ≡⟨ ap (F.₁ f) (has⊥ _ .centre .commute) ⟩≡ F.₁ f sect ∎ inv : ∀ x → Sets.is-invertible (nat .η x) inv x = Sets.make-invertible (λ f → F.₁ f (bot .section)) (funext λ x → ap hom $ has⊥ _ .paths (Co.elem-hom x refl)) (funext λ x → has⊥ _ .centre .commute) f-corep : Corepresentation F f-corep .corep = bot .ob f-corep .corepresents = [C,Sets].invertible→iso nat $ invertible→invertibleⁿ nat inv corepresentation→initial-element {F} F-corep = init where module F = Functor F module R = corep F-corep open Initial open Co.Element open Co.Element-hom init : Initial (Co.∫ F) init .bot .ob = F-corep .corep init .bot .section = R.from .η _ C.id init .has⊥ (Co.elem o s) .centre .hom = R.to .η _ s init .has⊥ (Co.elem o s) .centre .commute = F.₁ (R.to .η o s) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡˘⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩≡˘ R.from .η _ ⌜ R.to .η o s C.∘ C.id ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (C.idr _) ⟩≡ R.from .η _ (R.to .η o s) ≡⟨ unext R.invr o s ⟩≡ s ∎ init .has⊥ (Co.elem o s) .paths h = ext $ R.to .η o ⌜ s ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ comm ⟩≡˘ R.to .η o (R.from .η _ (h .hom)) ≡⟨ unext R.invl o _ ⟩≡ h .hom ∎ where comm = R.from .η _ ⌜ h .hom ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ (C.idr _) ⟩≡˘ R.from .η _ (h .hom C.∘ C.id) ≡⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩≡ F.₁ (h .hom) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡⟨ h .commute ⟩≡ s ∎
Corepresentable functors preserve limits🔗
A useful fact about corepresentable functors is that they preserve all limits. To show this, we first need to show that the covariant hom functor preserves limits.
To get an intuition for why this is true, consider how the functor
behaves on products. The set of morphisms
is equivalent to the set
of pairs of morphisms (See product-repr
for a proof of this equivalence).
Hom-from-preserves-limits : ∀ {o' κ'} → (c : C.Ob) → is-continuous o' κ' (Hom-from C c) Hom-from-preserves-limits c {Diagram = Dia} {K} {eps} lim = to-is-limitp ml (funext λ _ → refl) where open make-is-limit module lim = is-limit lim ml : make-is-limit _ _ ml .ψ j f = lim.ψ j C.∘ f ml .commutes f = funext λ g → C.pulll (sym (eps .is-natural _ _ _)) ∙ (C.elimr (K .F-id) C.⟩∘⟨refl) ml .universal eps p x = lim.universal (λ j → eps j x) (λ f → p f $ₚ x) ml .factors _ _ = funext λ _ → lim.factors _ _ ml .unique eps p other q = funext λ x → lim.unique _ _ _ λ j → q j $ₚ x
Preservation of limits by corepresentable functors then follows from a general fact about functors: if preserves limits, and is naturally isomorphic to then must also preserve limits.
corepresentable-preserves-limits : ∀ {o' κ'} {F} → Corepresentation F → is-continuous o' κ' F corepresentable-preserves-limits F-corep lim = natural-iso→preserves-limits (F-corep .corepresents ni⁻¹) (Hom-from-preserves-limits (F-corep .corep)) lim
We can show a similar fact for representable functors, but with a twist: they reverse colimits! This is due to the fact that a representable functor is contravariant. Specifically, will take limits in to limits in but limits in are colimits, so will take colimits in to limits in
A less formal perspective on this is that the collection of maps out of a colimit is still defined as a limit in For instance, to give a out of a coproduct, we are required to give a pair of maps and
よ-reverses-colimits : ∀ {o' κ'} → (c : C.Ob) → is-cocontinuous o' κ' (Functor.op (よ₀ C c)) よ-reverses-colimits c {Diagram = Dia} {K} {eta} colim = to-is-colimitp mc (funext λ _ → refl) where open make-is-colimit module colim = is-colimit colim mc : make-is-colimit _ _ mc .ψ j f = f C.∘ colim.ψ j mc .commutes f = funext λ g → C.pullr (eta .is-natural _ _ _) ∙ (C.refl⟩∘⟨ C.eliml (K .F-id)) mc .universal eta p x = colim.universal (λ j → eta j x) (λ f → p f $ₚ x) mc .factors eta p = funext λ _ → colim.factors _ _ mc .unique eta p other q = funext λ x → colim.unique _ _ _ λ j → q j $ₚ x representable-reverses-colimits : ∀ {o' κ'} {F} → Representation F → is-cocontinuous o' κ' (Functor.op F) representable-reverses-colimits F-rep colim = natural-iso→preserves-colimits ((F-rep .represents ni^op) ni⁻¹) (よ-reverses-colimits (F-rep .rep)) colim