open import Cat.Functor.Adjoint.Compose open import Cat.Functor.Naturality open import Cat.Functor.Properties open import Cat.Functor.Adjoint open import Cat.Functor.Base open import Cat.Prelude import Cat.Functor.Reasoning as Fr import Cat.Reasoning module Cat.Functor.Equivalence where
Equivalences🔗
A functor is an equivalence of categories when it has a right adjoint with the unit and counit natural transformations being natural isomorphisms. This immediately implies that our adjoint pair extends to an adjoint triple
record is-equivalence (F : Functor C D) : Type (adj-level C D) where private module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D module [C,C] = Cat.Reasoning Cat[ C , C ] module [D,D] = Cat.Reasoning Cat[ D , D ] field F⁻¹ : Functor D C F⊣F⁻¹ : F ⊣ F⁻¹ open _⊣_ F⊣F⁻¹ hiding (η ; ε) public field unit-iso : ∀ x → C.is-invertible (unit.η x) counit-iso : ∀ x → D.is-invertible (counit.ε x)
The first thing we note is that having a natural family of invertible morphisms gives isomorphisms in the respective functor categories:
F∘F⁻¹≅Id : (F F∘ F⁻¹) [D,D].≅ Id F∘F⁻¹≅Id = [D,D].invertible→iso counit (invertible→invertibleⁿ _ counit-iso) Id≅F⁻¹∘F : Id [C,C].≅ (F⁻¹ F∘ F) Id≅F⁻¹∘F = [C,C].invertible→iso unit (invertible→invertibleⁿ _ unit-iso) unit⁻¹ = [C,C]._≅_.from Id≅F⁻¹∘F counit⁻¹ = [D,D]._≅_.from F∘F⁻¹≅Id
F⁻¹⊣F : F⁻¹ ⊣ F F⁻¹⊣F = adj' where module adj = _⊣_ F⊣F⁻¹ open _⊣_ adj' : F⁻¹ ⊣ F adj' .unit = counit⁻¹ adj' .counit = unit⁻¹ adj' .zig {a} = zig' where abstract p : unit⁻¹ .η (F⁻¹ # a) ≡ F⁻¹ .F₁ (adj.ε _) p = unit⁻¹ .η _ ≡⟨ C.introl adj.zag ⟩≡ (F⁻¹ .F₁ (adj.ε _) C.∘ adj.η _) C.∘ unit⁻¹ .η _ ≡⟨ C.cancelr (unit-iso _ .C.is-invertible.invl) ⟩≡ F⁻¹ .F₁ (adj.ε _) ∎ zig' : unit⁻¹ .η (F⁻¹ # a) C.∘ F⁻¹ .F₁ (counit⁻¹ .η a) ≡ C.id zig' = ap₂ C._∘_ p refl ·· sym (F⁻¹ .F-∘ _ _) ·· ap (F⁻¹ .F₁) (counit-iso _ .D.is-invertible.invl) ∙ F⁻¹ .F-id adj' .zag {b} = zag' where abstract p : counit⁻¹ .η (F # b) ≡ F .F₁ (adj.η b) p = counit⁻¹ .η _ ≡⟨ D.intror adj.zig ⟩≡ counit⁻¹ .η _ D.∘ adj.ε _ D.∘ F .F₁ (adj.η b) ≡⟨ D.cancell (counit-iso _ .D.is-invertible.invr) ⟩≡ F .F₁ (adj.η b) ∎ zag' : F .F₁ (unit⁻¹ .η b) D.∘ counit⁻¹ .η (F # b) ≡ D.id zag' = ap₂ D._∘_ refl p ·· sym (F .F-∘ _ _) ·· ap (F .F₁) (unit-iso _ .C.is-invertible.invr) ∙ F .F-id inverse-equivalence : is-equivalence F⁻¹ inverse-equivalence = record { F⁻¹ = F ; F⊣F⁻¹ = F⁻¹⊣F ; unit-iso = λ x → D.is-invertible-inverse (counit-iso _) ; counit-iso = λ x → C.is-invertible-inverse (unit-iso _) }
We chose, for definiteness, the above definition of equivalence of categories, since it provides convenient access to the most useful data: The induced natural isomorphisms, the adjunction unit/counit, and the triangle identities. It is a lot of data to come up with by hand, though, so we provide some alternatives:
Fully faithful, essentially surjective🔗
Any fully faithful and (split!) essentially surjective functor determines an equivalence of precategories. Recall that “split essentially surjective” means we have some determined procedure for picking out an essential fibre over any object an object together with a specified isomorphism
module _ {F : Functor C D} (ff : is-fully-faithful F) (eso : is-split-eso F) where import Cat.Reasoning C as C import Cat.Reasoning D as D private module di = D._≅_ private ff⁻¹ : ∀ {x y} → D.Hom (F .F₀ x) (F .F₀ y) → C.Hom _ _ ff⁻¹ = equiv→inverse ff module ff {x} {y} = Equiv (_ , ff {x} {y})
It remains to show that, when is fully faithful, this assignment of essential fibres extends to a functor For the object part, we send to the specified preimage. For the morphism part, the splitting gives us isomorphisms and so that we may form the composite Fullness then completes the construction.
ff+split-eso→inverse : Functor D C ff+split-eso→inverse .F₀ x = eso x .fst ff+split-eso→inverse .F₁ {x} {y} f = ff⁻¹ (f*y-iso .D._≅_.from D.∘ f D.∘ f*x-iso .D._≅_.to) where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) open Σ (eso y) renaming (fst to f*y ; snd to f*y-iso)
We must then, as usual, prove that this definition preserves identities and distributes over composites, so that we really have a functor. Preservation of identities is immediate; Distribution over composites is by faithfulness.
ff+split-eso→inverse .F-id {x} = ff⁻¹ (f*x-iso .di.from D.∘ ⌜ D.id D.∘ f*x-iso .di.to ⌝) ≡⟨ ap! (D.idl _) ⟩≡ ff⁻¹ (f*x-iso .di.from D.∘ f*x-iso .di.to) ≡⟨ ap ff⁻¹ (f*x-iso .di.invr) ⟩≡ ff⁻¹ D.id ≡˘⟨ ap ff⁻¹ (F .F-id) ⟩≡˘ ff⁻¹ (F .F₁ C.id) ≡⟨ ff.η _ ⟩≡ C.id ∎ where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) ff+split-eso→inverse .F-∘ {x} {y} {z} f g = ff→faithful {F = F} ff ( F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ (ffz D.∘ (f D.∘ g) D.∘ ftx)) ≡⟨ ff.ε _ ⟩≡ ffz D.∘ (f D.∘ g) D.∘ ftx ≡⟨ cat! D ⟩≡ ffz D.∘ f D.∘ ⌜ D.id ⌝ D.∘ g D.∘ ftx ≡˘⟨ ap¡ (f*y-iso .di.invl) ⟩≡˘ ffz D.∘ f D.∘ (fty D.∘ ffy) D.∘ g D.∘ ftx ≡⟨ cat! D ⟩≡ (ffz D.∘ f D.∘ fty) D.∘ (ffy D.∘ g D.∘ ftx) ≡˘⟨ ap₂ D._∘_ (ff.ε _) (ff.ε _) ⟩≡˘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ _) D.∘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ _) ≡˘⟨ F .F-∘ _ _ ⟩≡˘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ _ C.∘ ff⁻¹ _) ∎ ) where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) open Σ (eso y) renaming (fst to f*y ; snd to f*y-iso) open Σ (eso z) renaming (fst to f*z ; snd to f*z-iso) ffz = f*z-iso .di.from ftz = f*z-iso .di.to ffy = f*y-iso .di.from fty = f*y-iso .di.to ffx = f*x-iso .di.from ftx = f*x-iso .di.to
We will, for brevity, refer to the functor we’ve just built as
rather than its “proper name” ff+split-eso→inverse
. Hercules
now only has 11 labours to go: We must construct unit and counit natural
transformations, prove that they satisfy the triangle identities, and
prove that the unit/counit we define are componentwise invertible. I’ll
keep the proofs of naturality in <details>
tags
since.. they’re rough.
private G = ff+split-eso→inverse
For the unit, we have an object and we’re asked to provide a morphism — where, recall, the notation represents the chosen essential fibre of over By fullness, it suffices to provide a morphism But recall that the essential fibre comes equipped with an isomorphism
ff+split-eso→unit : Id => (G F∘ F) ff+split-eso→unit .η x = ff⁻¹ (f*x-iso .di.from) where open Σ (eso (F # x)) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso)
Naturality of ff+split-eso→unit
.
ff+split-eso→unit .is-natural x y f = ff→faithful {F = F} ff ( F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffy C.∘ f) ≡⟨ F .F-∘ _ _ ⟩≡ ⌜ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffy) ⌝ D.∘ F .F₁ f ≡⟨ ap! (ff.ε _) ⟩≡ ffy D.∘ ⌜ F .F₁ f ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (sym (D.idr _) ∙ ap (F .F₁ f D.∘_) (sym (f*x-iso .di.invl))) ⟩≡ ffy D.∘ F .F₁ f D.∘ ftx D.∘ ffx ≡⟨ cat! D ⟩≡ (ffy D.∘ F .F₁ f D.∘ ftx) D.∘ ffx ≡˘⟨ ap₂ D._∘_ (ff.ε _) (ff.ε _) ⟩≡˘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ (ffy D.∘ F .F₁ f D.∘ ftx)) D.∘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffx) ≡˘⟨ F .F-∘ _ _ ⟩≡˘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ (ffy D.∘ F .F₁ f D.∘ ftx) C.∘ ff⁻¹ ffx) ≡⟨⟩ F .F₁ ((G F∘ F) .F₁ f C.∘ x→f*x) ∎ ) where open Σ (eso (F .F₀ x)) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) open Σ (eso (F .F₀ y)) renaming (fst to f*y ; snd to f*y-iso) ffy = f*y-iso .di.from fty = f*y-iso .di.to ffx = f*x-iso .di.from ftx = f*x-iso .di.to x→f*x : C.Hom x f*x x→f*x = ff⁻¹ (f*x-iso .di.from) y→f*y : C.Hom y f*y y→f*y = ff⁻¹ (f*y-iso .di.from)
For the counit, we have to provide a morphism We can again pick the given isomorphism.
ff+split-eso→counit : (F F∘ G) => Id ff+split-eso→counit .η x = f*x-iso .di.to where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso)
Naturality of ff+split-eso→counit
ff+split-eso→counit .is-natural x y f = fty D.∘ ⌜ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ (ffy D.∘ f D.∘ ftx)) ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (ff.ε _) ⟩≡ fty D.∘ ffy D.∘ f D.∘ ftx ≡⟨ D.cancell (f*y-iso .di.invl) ⟩≡ f D.∘ ftx ∎ where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) open Σ (eso y) renaming (fst to f*y ; snd to f*y-iso) ffy = f*y-iso .di.from fty = f*y-iso .di.to ftx = f*x-iso .di.to
Checking the triangle identities, and that the adjunction unit/counit defined above are natural isomorphisms, is routine. We present the calculations without commentary:
open _⊣_ ff+split-eso→F⊣inverse : F ⊣ G ff+split-eso→F⊣inverse .unit = ff+split-eso→unit ff+split-eso→F⊣inverse .counit = ff+split-eso→counit ff+split-eso→F⊣inverse .zig {x} = ftx D.∘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffx) ≡⟨ ap (ftx D.∘_) (ff.ε _) ⟩≡ ftx D.∘ ffx ≡⟨ f*x-iso .di.invl ⟩≡ D.id ∎
where open Σ (eso (F .F₀ x)) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) ffx = f*x-iso .di.from ftx = f*x-iso .di.to
The zag
identity needs an appeal to
faithfulness:
ff+split-eso→F⊣inverse .zag {x} = ff→faithful {F = F} ff ( F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ (ffx D.∘ ftx D.∘ fftx) C.∘ ff⁻¹ fffx) ≡⟨ F .F-∘ _ _ ⟩≡ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ (ffx D.∘ ftx D.∘ fftx)) D.∘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ fffx) ≡⟨ ap₂ D._∘_ (ff.ε _) (ff.ε _) ⟩≡ (ffx D.∘ ftx D.∘ fftx) D.∘ fffx ≡⟨ cat! D ⟩≡ (ffx D.∘ ftx) D.∘ (fftx D.∘ fffx) ≡⟨ ap₂ D._∘_ (f*x-iso .di.invr) (f*f*x-iso .di.invl) ⟩≡ D.id D.∘ D.id ≡⟨ D.idl _ ∙ sym (F .F-id) ⟩≡ F .F₁ C.id ∎ )
Now to show they are componentwise invertible:
where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) open Σ (eso (F .F₀ f*x)) renaming (fst to f*f*x ; snd to f*f*x-iso) ffx = f*x-iso .di.from ftx = f*x-iso .di.to fffx = f*f*x-iso .di.from fftx = f*f*x-iso .di.to
open is-equivalence ff+split-eso→is-equivalence : is-equivalence F ff+split-eso→is-equivalence .F⁻¹ = G ff+split-eso→is-equivalence .F⊣F⁻¹ = ff+split-eso→F⊣inverse ff+split-eso→is-equivalence .counit-iso x = record { inv = f*x-iso .di.from ; inverses = record { invl = f*x-iso .di.invl ; invr = f*x-iso .di.invr } } where open Σ (eso x) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso)
Since the unit is defined in terms of fullness, showing it is invertible needs an appeal to faithfulness (two, actually):
ff+split-eso→is-equivalence .unit-iso x = record { inv = ff⁻¹ (f*x-iso .di.to) ; inverses = record { invl = ff→faithful {F = F} ff ( F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffx C.∘ ff⁻¹ ftx) ≡⟨ F .F-∘ _ _ ⟩≡ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffx) D.∘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ftx) ≡⟨ ap₂ D._∘_ (ff.ε _) (ff.ε _) ⟩≡ ffx D.∘ ftx ≡⟨ f*x-iso .di.invr ⟩≡ D.id ≡˘⟨ F .F-id ⟩≡˘ F .F₁ C.id ∎) ; invr = ff→faithful {F = F} ff ( F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ftx C.∘ ff⁻¹ ffx) ≡⟨ F .F-∘ _ _ ⟩≡ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ftx) D.∘ F .F₁ (ff⁻¹ ffx) ≡⟨ ap₂ D._∘_ (ff.ε _) (ff.ε _) ⟩≡ ftx D.∘ ffx ≡⟨ f*x-iso .di.invl ⟩≡ D.id ≡˘⟨ F .F-id ⟩≡˘ F .F₁ C.id ∎) } } where open Σ (eso (F .F₀ x)) renaming (fst to f*x ; snd to f*x-iso) ffx = f*x-iso .di.from ftx = f*x-iso .di.to
Between categories🔗
Above, we made an equivalence out of any fully faithful and split essentially surjective functor. In set-theoretic mathematics (and indeed between strict categories), the splitting condition can not be lifted constructively: the statement “every (ff, eso) functor between strict categories is an equivalence” is equivalent to the axiom of choice.
However, between univalent categories, the situation is different: Any essentially surjective fully faithful functor splits. In particular, any ff functor between univalent categories has propositional essential fibres, so a “mere” essential surjection is automatically split. However, note that both the domain and codomain have to be categories for the argument to go through.
module _ (F : Functor C D) (ccat : is-category C) (dcat : is-category D) (ff : is-fully-faithful F) where private module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D
So, suppose we have categories and together with a fully faithful functor For any we’re given an inhabitant of which we want to “get out” from under the truncation. For this, we’ll show that the type being truncated is a proposition, so that we may “untruncate” it.
Essential-fibre-between-cats-is-prop : ∀ y → is-prop (Essential-fibre F y) Essential-fibre-between-cats-is-prop z (x , i) (y , j) = they're-equal where
For this magic trick, assume we’re given a
together with objects
and isomorphisms
and
We must show that
and that over this path,
Since
is fully faithful, we can find an isomorphism
in
which
sends back to
Fx≅Fy : F .F₀ x D.≅ F .F₀ y Fx≅Fy = j D.Iso⁻¹ D.∘Iso i x≅y : x C.≅ y x≅y = is-ff→essentially-injective {F = F} ff Fx≅Fy
Furthermore, since we’re working with categories, these isomorphisms restrict to paths and We’re half-done: we’ve shown that some exists, and it remains to show that over this path we have More specifically, we must give a path laying over
x≡y : x ≡ y x≡y = ccat .to-path x≅y Fx≡Fy : F .F₀ x ≡ F .F₀ y Fx≡Fy = dcat .to-path Fx≅Fy
Rather than showing it over
directly, we’ll show it over the path
we constructed independently. This is because we can use the helper
Hom-pathp-reflr-iso
to establish
the result with far less computation:
over' : PathP (λ i → Fx≡Fy i D.≅ z) i j over' = D.≅-pathp Fx≡Fy refl (Univalent.Hom-pathp-refll-iso dcat (D.cancell (i .D._≅_.invl)))
We must then connect with this path But since we originally got by full faithfulness of they are indeed the same path:
abstract square : ap# F x≡y ≡ Fx≡Fy square = ap# F x≡y ≡⟨ F-map-path F ccat dcat x≅y ⟩≡ dcat .to-path ⌜ F-map-iso F x≅y ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (equiv→counit (is-ff→F-map-iso-is-equiv {F = F} ff) _) ⟩≡ dcat .to-path Fx≅Fy ∎ over : PathP (λ i → F .F₀ (x≡y i) D.≅ z) i j over = transport (λ l → PathP (λ m → square (~ l) m D.≅ z) i j) over'
Hence — blink and you’ll miss it — the essential fibres of over any are propositions, so it suffices for them to be merely inhabited for the functor to be split eso. With tongue firmly in cheek we call this result the theorem of choice.
they're-equal = Σ-pathp x≡y over Theorem-of-choice : is-eso F → is-split-eso F Theorem-of-choice eso y = ∥-∥-elim (λ _ → Essential-fibre-between-cats-is-prop y) (λ x → x) (eso y)
This theorem implies that any fully faithful, “merely” essentially surjective functor between categories is an equivalence:
ff+eso→is-equivalence : is-eso F → is-equivalence F ff+eso→is-equivalence eso = ff+split-eso→is-equivalence ff (Theorem-of-choice eso)
Furthermore, if is an equivalence between categories, then it’s an equivalence-on-objects functor. The inverse functor gives us a way to turn objects of back into objects of and unit/counit of the equivalence ensure that and so all that remains is to use the fact that and are categories to get the requisite paths.
is-cat-equivalence→equiv-on-objects : ∀ {F : Functor C D} → (ccat : is-category C) (dcat : is-category D) → is-equivalence F → is-equiv-on-objects F is-cat-equivalence→equiv-on-objects {C = C} {D = D} {F = F} ccat dcat eqv = is-iso→is-equiv $ iso (e.F⁻¹ .F₀) (λ d → dcat .to-path (D.invertible→iso _ (e.counit-iso d))) (λ c → sym $ ccat .to-path (C.invertible→iso _ (e.unit-iso c))) where module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D module e = is-equivalence eqv
Isomorphisms🔗
Another, more direct way of proving that a functor is an equivalence of precategories is proving that it is an isomorphism of precategories: It’s fully faithful, thus a typal equivalence of morphisms, and in addition its action on objects is an equivalence of types.
record is-precat-iso (F : Functor C D) : Type (adj-level C D) where no-eta-equality constructor iso field has-is-ff : is-fully-faithful F has-is-iso : is-equiv (F .F₀)
Such a functor is (immediately) fully faithful, and the inverse has-is-iso
means that it is split
essentially surjective; For given
the inverse of
gives us an object
We must then provide an isomorphism
but those are identical, hence isomorphic.
module _ {F : Functor C D} (p : is-precat-iso F) where open is-precat-iso p is-precat-iso→is-split-eso : is-split-eso F is-precat-iso→is-split-eso ob = equiv→inverse has-is-iso ob , isom where isom = path→iso {C = D} (equiv→counit has-is-iso _)
Thus, by the theorem above, is an adjoint equivalence of precategories.
is-precat-iso→is-equivalence : is-equivalence F is-precat-iso→is-equivalence = ff+split-eso→is-equivalence has-is-ff is-precat-iso→is-split-eso
open is-equivalence open Precategory open _⊣_ unquoteDecl H-Level-is-precat-iso = declare-record-hlevel 1 H-Level-is-precat-iso (quote is-precat-iso) module _ {o ℓ o' ℓ'} {C : Precategory o ℓ} {D : Precategory o' ℓ'} (F : Functor C D) (eqv : is-equivalence F) where private module e = is-equivalence eqv module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D module F = Fr F is-equivalence→is-ff : is-fully-faithful F is-equivalence→is-ff = is-iso→is-equiv λ where .is-iso.inv x → e.unit⁻¹ .η _ C.∘ L-adjunct e.F⊣F⁻¹ x .is-iso.rinv x → D.invertible→monic (F-map-invertible F (e.unit-iso _)) _ _ $ ap₂ D._∘_ refl (F .F-∘ _ _) ·· D.cancell (F.annihilate (e.unit-iso _ .C.is-invertible.invl)) ·· D.invertible→monic (e.counit-iso _) _ _ (R-L-adjunct e.F⊣F⁻¹ x ∙ sym (D.cancell e.zig)) .is-iso.linv x → ap (_ C.∘_) (sym (e.unit .is-natural _ _ _)) ∙ C.cancell (e.unit-iso _ .C.is-invertible.invr) is-equivalence→is-split-eso : is-split-eso F is-equivalence→is-split-eso y = (e.F⁻¹ .F₀ y) , D.invertible→iso (e.counit .η y) (e.counit-iso y) is-equivalence→is-eso : is-eso F is-equivalence→is-eso y = inc ((e.F⁻¹ .F₀ y) , D.invertible→iso (e.counit .η y) (e.counit-iso y)) open is-precat-iso open is-iso is-equivalence→is-precat-iso : is-category C → is-category D → is-precat-iso F is-equivalence→is-precat-iso c-cat d-cat .has-is-ff = is-equivalence→is-ff is-equivalence→is-precat-iso c-cat d-cat .has-is-iso = is-cat-equivalence→equiv-on-objects c-cat d-cat eqv
record Equivalence {o ℓ o' ℓ'} (C : Precategory o ℓ) (D : Precategory o' ℓ') : Type (o ⊔ ℓ ⊔ o' ⊔ ℓ') where no-eta-equality field To : Functor C D To-equiv : is-equivalence To open is-equivalence To-equiv renaming (F⁻¹ to From; F⊣F⁻¹ to To⊣From) public
Properties of equivalences🔗
If is fully-faithfuly and essentially surjective, then for every hom-set there (merely) exists an equivalent hom-set
module _ {oc ℓc od ℓd} {C : Precategory oc ℓc} {D : Precategory od ℓd} where private module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D
ff+split-eso→hom-equiv : (F : Functor C D) → is-fully-faithful F → is-split-eso F → ∀ d d' → Σ[ c ∈ C ] Σ[ c' ∈ C ] (C.Hom c c' ≃ D.Hom d d') ff+split-eso→hom-equiv F ff split-eso d d' = d-fib .fst , d'-fib .fst , (F .F₁ , ff) ∙e D.iso→hom-equiv (d-fib .snd) (d'-fib .snd) where d-fib = split-eso d d'-fib = split-eso d' ff+eso→hom-equiv : (F : Functor C D) → is-fully-faithful F → is-eso F → ∀ d d' → ∃[ c ∈ C ] Σ[ c' ∈ C ] (C.Hom c c' ≃ D.Hom d d') ff+eso→hom-equiv F ff eso d d' = do (c , Fc≅d) ← eso d (c' , Fc'≅d') ← eso d' pure (c , c' , (F .F₁ , ff) ∙e D.iso→hom-equiv Fc≅d Fc'≅d')
This allows us to prove a very useful little lemma: if is a fully-faithful, essentially surjective functor, then any property of hom-sets of that holds for all hom-sets must also hold for all hom-sets of
ff+eso→preserves-hom-props : ∀ {ℓ} (F : Functor C D) → is-fully-faithful F → is-eso F → (P : Type (ℓc ⊔ ℓd) → Type ℓ) → (∀ A → is-prop (P A)) → (∀ c c' → P (Lift ℓd (C.Hom c c'))) → ∀ d d' → P (Lift ℓc (D.Hom d d')) ff+eso→preserves-hom-props F ff eso P prop P-hom d d' = ∥-∥-out (prop (Lift ℓc (D.Hom d d'))) $ do (c , c' , eqv) ← ff+eso→hom-equiv F ff eso d d' pure (transport (ap P (ua (Lift-ap eqv))) (P-hom c c'))
As a corollary, we note that if is a fully-faithful, essentially surjective functor, then if the hom-sets of are all then the hom-sets of must also be
ff+eso→hom-hlevel : ∀ {n} (F : Functor C D) → is-fully-faithful F → is-eso F → (∀ c c' → is-hlevel (C.Hom c c') n) → ∀ d d' → is-hlevel (D.Hom d d') n ff+eso→hom-hlevel {n = n} F ff eso C-hlevel d d' = Lift-is-hlevel' _ $ ff+eso→preserves-hom-props F ff eso (λ A → is-hlevel A n) (λ _ → is-hlevel-is-prop n) (λ c c' → Lift-is-hlevel n (C-hlevel c c')) d d'
Note that if is fully faithful and split essentially surjective, then we can drop the requirement that must be a prop.
ff+split-eso→preserves-hom-fams : ∀ {ℓ} (F : Functor C D) → is-fully-faithful F → is-split-eso F → (P : Type (ℓc ⊔ ℓd) → Type ℓ) → (∀ c c' → P (Lift ℓd (C.Hom c c'))) → ∀ d d' → P (Lift ℓc (D.Hom d d')) ff+split-eso→preserves-hom-fams F ff split-eso P P-hom d d' = transport (ap P (ua (Lift-ap (ff+split-eso→hom-equiv F ff split-eso d d' .snd .snd)))) (P-hom _ _)
As a corollary, equivalences preserve all families over hom sets.
equivalence→preserves-hom-fams : ∀ {ℓ} (E : Equivalence C D) → (P : Type (ℓc ⊔ ℓd) → Type ℓ) → (∀ c c' → P (Lift ℓd (C.Hom c c'))) → ∀ d d' → P (Lift ℓc (D.Hom d d')) equivalence→preserves-hom-fams E = ff+split-eso→preserves-hom-fams (Equivalence.To E) (is-equivalence→is-ff _ (Equivalence.To-equiv E)) (is-equivalence→is-split-eso _ (Equivalence.To-equiv E))
equivalence→hom-hlevel : ∀ {n} (E : Equivalence C D) → (∀ c c' → is-hlevel (C.Hom c c') n) → ∀ d d' → is-hlevel (D.Hom d d') n equivalence→hom-hlevel {n = n} E C-hlevel d d' = Lift-is-hlevel' n $ equivalence→preserves-hom-fams E (λ A → is-hlevel A n) (λ c c' → Lift-is-hlevel n (C-hlevel c c')) d d'
Being an equivalence is also invariant under natural isomorphism.
is-equivalence-natural-iso : ∀ {F G : Functor C D} → F ≅ⁿ G → is-equivalence F → is-equivalence G is-equivalence-natural-iso {C = C} {D = D} {F = F} {G = G} α F-eqv = G-eqv where open is-equivalence module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D G-eqv : is-equivalence G G-eqv .F⁻¹ = F-eqv .F⁻¹ G-eqv .F⊣F⁻¹ = adjoint-natural-isol α (F-eqv .F⊣F⁻¹) G-eqv .unit-iso x = C.invertible-∘ (C.invertible-∘ (F-map-invertible (F-eqv .F⁻¹) (isoⁿ→is-invertible α x)) C.id-invertible) (F-eqv .unit-iso x) G-eqv .counit-iso x = D.invertible-∘ (F-eqv .counit-iso x) (D.invertible-∘ (F-map-invertible F C.id-invertible) (isoⁿ→is-invertible α _ D.invertible⁻¹))
Equivalences are invertible.
_Equivalence⁻¹ : Equivalence C D → Equivalence D C (E Equivalence⁻¹) .Equivalence.To = Equivalence.From E (E Equivalence⁻¹) .Equivalence.To-equiv = Equivalence.inverse-equivalence E
Equivalences are also composable, as adjoints compose.
is-equivalence-∘ : ∀ {F : Functor D E} {G : Functor C D} → is-equivalence F → is-equivalence G → is-equivalence (F F∘ G) is-equivalence-∘ {E = E} {C = C} {F = F} {G = G} F-eqv G-eqv = FG-eqv where module F-eqv = is-equivalence F-eqv module G-eqv = is-equivalence G-eqv module C = Cat.Reasoning C module E = Cat.Reasoning E FG-eqv : is-equivalence (F F∘ G) FG-eqv .F⁻¹ = G-eqv.F⁻¹ F∘ F-eqv.F⁻¹ FG-eqv .F⊣F⁻¹ = LF⊣GR G-eqv.F⊣F⁻¹ F-eqv.F⊣F⁻¹ FG-eqv .unit-iso x = C.invertible-∘ (F-map-invertible G-eqv.F⁻¹ (F-eqv.unit-iso (G .F₀ x))) (G-eqv.unit-iso x) FG-eqv .counit-iso x = E.invertible-∘ (F-eqv.counit-iso x) (F-map-invertible F (G-eqv.counit-iso (F-eqv .F⁻¹ .F₀ x))) _∘Equivalence_ : Equivalence C D → Equivalence D E → Equivalence C E (F ∘Equivalence G) .Equivalence.To = Equivalence.To G F∘ Equivalence.To F (F ∘Equivalence G) .Equivalence.To-equiv = is-equivalence-∘ (Equivalence.To-equiv G) (Equivalence.To-equiv F)
Unsurprisingly, the identity functor is an equivalence.
Id-is-equivalence : ∀ {o h} {C : Precategory o h} → is-equivalence {C = C} Id Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⁻¹ = Id Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⊣F⁻¹ .unit .η x = C .id Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⊣F⁻¹ .unit .is-natural x y f = C .idl _ ∙ sym (C .idr _) Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⊣F⁻¹ .counit .η x = C .id Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⊣F⁻¹ .counit .is-natural x y f = C .idl _ ∙ sym (C .idr _) Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⊣F⁻¹ .zig = C .idl _ Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .F⊣F⁻¹ .zag = C .idl _ Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .unit-iso x = Cat.Reasoning.make-invertible C (C .id) (C .idl _) (C .idl _) Id-is-equivalence {C = C} .counit-iso x = Cat.Reasoning.make-invertible C (C .id) (C .idl _) (C .idl _)
Preserving invertibility🔗
We can characterise equivalences as those adjunctions that preserve invertibility, in the sense that the adjunct of an isomorphism is an isomorphism and vice versa; that is, the property of being invertible in is equivalent to the property of being invertible in over the adjunction’s
module _ {o ℓ o' ℓ'} {C : Precategory o ℓ} {D : Precategory o' ℓ'} {L : Functor C D} {R : Functor D C} (L⊣R : L ⊣ R) where private module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D module L = Fr L module R = Fr R
preserves-invertibility : Type (o ⊔ ℓ ⊔ o' ⊔ ℓ') preserves-invertibility = ∀ {a b} → D.is-invertible ≃[ adjunct-hom-equiv L⊣R {a} {b} ] C.is-invertible
Since the unit and counit of an adjunction are adjuncts of identities, it’s not hard to see that they must be invertible if the adjunction preserves invertibility.
preserves-invertibility→equivalence : preserves-invertibility → is-equivalence L preserves-invertibility→equivalence e .F⁻¹ = R preserves-invertibility→equivalence e .F⊣F⁻¹ = L⊣R preserves-invertibility→equivalence e .unit-iso c = C.invertible-cancelr (R.F-map-invertible D.id-invertible) (Equiv.to (e D.id _ refl) D.id-invertible) preserves-invertibility→equivalence e .counit-iso d = D.invertible-cancell (L.F-map-invertible C.id-invertible) (Equiv.from (e _ _ (L-R-adjunct L⊣R _)) C.id-invertible)
The other direction is just as straightforward, since adjuncts are defined by composition with the (co)unit, and isomorphisms compose.
module _ {o ℓ o' ℓ'} {C : Precategory o ℓ} {D : Precategory o' ℓ'} (F : Functor C D) (eqv : is-equivalence F) where private module e = is-equivalence eqv module C = Cat.Reasoning C module D = Cat.Reasoning D module F = Fr F module F⁻¹ = Fr e.F⁻¹
equivalence→preserves-invertibility : preserves-invertibility e.F⊣F⁻¹ equivalence→preserves-invertibility = prop-over-ext (adjunct-hom-equiv e.F⊣F⁻¹) (hlevel 1) (hlevel 1) (λ f inv → C.invertible-∘ (F⁻¹.F-map-invertible inv) (e.unit-iso _)) (λ f inv → D.invertible-∘ (e.counit-iso _) (F.F-map-invertible inv))