module 1Lab.Univalence where
Univalenceπ
In Homotopy Type Theory, univalence is the principle stating that equivalent types can be identified. When the book first came out, there was no widely-accepted computational interpretation of this principle, so it was added to the theory as an axiom: the univalence axiom.
Precisely, the axiom as presented in the book consists of the following data (right under remark Β§2.10.4):
A map which turns equivalences into identifications of types. This map is called
ua
.A rule for eliminating identifications of types, by turning them into equivalences:
pathβequiv
The propositional computation rule, stating that transport along
ua(f)
is identical to applyingf
:uaΞ²
.
In the book, there is an extra postulated datum asserting that ua
is an inverse to pathβequiv
. This datum
does not have a name in this development, because itβs proved in-line in
the construction of the term univalence
.
The point of cubical type theory is to give these terms constructive interpretations, i.e., make them definable in the theory, in terms of constructions that have computational behaviour. Letβs see how this is done.
Glueπ
To even state univalence, we first have to make sure that the concept of βpaths between typesβ makes sense in the first place. In βBook HoTTβ, paths between types are a well-formed concept because the path type is uniformly inductively defined for everything β including universes. This is not the case in Cubical type theory, where for paths in to be well-behaved, must be fibrant.
Since thereβs no obvious choice for how to interpret hcomp
in Type
, a fine solution is to
make hcomp
its own type former.
This is the approach taken by some Cubical type theories in the RedPRL school. Univalence in those type
theories is then achieved by adding a type former, called
V
, which turns an equivalence into a path.
In CCHM (2016)
β and therefore Cubical Agda β a different approach is taken, which
combines proving univalence with defining a fibrancy structure for the
universe. The core idea is to define a new type former, Glue
, which βgluesβ a partial type, along an equivalence,
to a total type.
private variable β β' β'' β''' : Level A Aβ Aβ B Bβ Bβ C Cβ Cβ : Type β private primitive primGlue : (A : Type β) {Ο : I} β (T : Partial Ο (Type β')) β (e : PartialP Ο (Ξ» o β T o β A)) β Type β' prim^glue : {A : Type β} {Ο : I} β {T : Partial Ο (Type β')} β {e : PartialP Ο (Ξ» o β T o β A)} β PartialP Ο T β A β primGlue A T e prim^unglue : {A : Type β} {Ο : I} β {T : Partial Ο (Type β')} β {e : PartialP Ο (Ξ» o β T o β A)} β primGlue A T e β A open import Prim.HCompU open import 1Lab.Equiv.FromPath
Glue : (A : Type β) β {Ο : I} β (Te : Partial Ο (Ξ£[ T β Type β' ] T β A)) β Type β'
The public interface of Glue
demands a type
called the base type, a formula
and a partial type
which is equivalent to
Since the equivalence is defined inside the partial element, it
can also (potentially) vary over the interval, so in reality we have a
family of partial types
and a family of partial equivalences
In the specific case where we set
we can illustrate Glue A (T, f)
as the dashed line in the
square diagram below. The conceptual idea is that by βgluingβ
onto a totally defined type, we get a type which extends
Glue A {Ο} Te = primGlue A tys eqvs module glue-sys where tys : Partial Ο (Type _) tys (Ο = i1) = Te 1=1 .fst eqvs : PartialP Ο (Ξ» .o β tys _ β A) eqvs (Ο = i1) = Te 1=1 .snd unattach : {A : Type β} (Ο : I) {T : Partial Ο (Type β')} {e : PartialP Ο (Ξ» o β T o β A)} β primGlue A T e β A unattach Ο = prim^unglue {Ο = Ο} attach : {A : Type β} (Ο : I) {T : Partial Ο (Type β')} {e : PartialP Ο (Ξ» o β T o β A)} β (p : PartialP Ο T) β A [ Ο β¦ (Ξ» o β e o .fst (p o)) ] β primGlue A T e attach Ο p x = prim^glue {Ο = Ο} p (outS x) -- Display of primGlue -- ------------------- -- -- We can't in general recover a pretty Glue application from an -- internal 'primGlue', since display forms can't do higher order -- matching. -- -- But we can instead use a *named* system in the definition -- of important 'Glue's, and then match on this definition when trying -- to unapply 'primGlue'. -- -- Since 'primGlue' is private, the only way to glue things is using the -- nice interface, so 'Glue's display nicely. {-# DISPLAY primGlue A (glue-sys.tys _ Te) (glue-sys.eqvs _ Te) = Glue A Te #-} {-# DISPLAY prim^unglue {l} {l'} {A} {Ο} {t} {e} x = unattach {l} {l'} {A} Ο {t} {e} x #-} {-# DISPLAY prim^glue {_} {_} {_} {Ο} {_} {_} x y = attach Ο x y #-}
For Glue
to
extend
we add a computation rule which could be called a boundary
condition, since it specifies how Glue
behaves on the
boundaries of cubes. Concisely, when
we have that Glue
evaluates to the partial type. This is exactly what it means for Glue
to extend
module _ {A B : Type} {e : A β B} where private Glue-boundary : Glue B {i1} (Ξ» x β A , e) β‘ A Glue-boundary i = A
Furthermore, since we can turn any family of paths into a family of
equivalences, we can use the Glue
construct to implement
something with precisely the same interface as hcomp
for Type
:
glue-hfill : β {β} Ο (u : β i β Partial (Ο β¨ ~ i) (Type β)) β β i β Type β [ _ β¦ (Ξ» { (i = i0) β u i0 1=1 ; (Ο = i1) β u i 1=1 }) ]
The type of glue-hfill
is the same as that of hfill
,
but the type is stated much more verbosely β so that we may define it
without previous reference to a hcomp
analogue. Like hfill
, glue-hfill
extends an open
box of types to a totally-defined cube. The type of glue-hfill
expresses this
in terms of extensions: We have a path (thatβs the β i β
binder) of Type
s
which agrees with outS u0
on the left endpoint, and with
u
everywhere.
glue-hfill Ο u i = inS ( Glue (u i0 1=1) {Ο = Ο β¨ ~ i} Ξ» { (Ο = i1) β u i 1=1 , lineβequiv (Ξ» j β u (i β§ ~ j) 1=1) ; (i = i0) β u i0 1=1 , lineβequiv (Ξ» i β u i0 1=1) })
In the case for
we must glue
onto itself using the identity equivalence. This guarantees that the
boundary of the stated type for glue-hfill
is satisfied.
However, since different faces of partial elements must agree where they
are defined, we can not use the identity equivalence directly, since
lineβequiv refl
is not definitionally the identity
equivalence.
When hence where is defined, we glue the endpoint onto using the equivalence generated by the path provided by itself! Itβs a family of partial paths, after all, and that can be turned into a family of partial equivalences.
Using hcomp-unique
and glue-hfill
together, we get
a internal characterisation of the fibrancy structure of the universe.
While hcomp-unique
may appear
surprising, it is essentially a generalisation of the uniqueness of path
compositions: Any open box has a contractible space of fillers.
hcompβ‘Glue : β {β} {Ο} (u : β i β Partial (Ο β¨ ~ i) (Type β)) β hcomp Ο u β‘ Glue (u i0 1=1) (Ξ» { (Ο = i1) β u i1 1=1 , lineβequiv (Ξ» j β u (~ j) 1=1) }) hcompβ‘Glue {Ο = Ο} u = hcomp-unique Ο u (glue-hfill Ο u)
Paths from Glueπ
Since Glue
generalises hcomp
by
allowing a partial equivalence as its βtubeβ, rather than a partial
path, it allows us to turn any equivalence into a path, using a sort of
βtrickβ: We consider the line with endpoints
and
as an open cube to be filled. A filler for this line is exactly a path
Since Glue
fills
open boxes of types using equivalences, this path exists!
ua : {A B : Type β} β A β B β A β‘ B ua {A = A} {B} eqv i = Glue B Ξ» where (i = i0) β A , eqv (i = i1) β B , _ , id-equiv
-- We use two named systems for the definition of 'ua' so that we can -- make the Glue display away ua : {A B : Type β} β A β B β A β‘ B ua {A = A} {B} eqv i = primGlue B tys eqvs module ua-sys where tys : Partial (β i) (Type _) tys (i = i0) = A tys (i = i1) = B eqvs : PartialP (β i) (Ξ» .o β tys o β B) eqvs (i = i0) = eqv eqvs (i = i1) = idβ -- see "Display of primGlue" above {-# DISPLAY primGlue _ (ua-sys.tys e i) (ua-sys.eqvs _ _) = ua e i #-}
Semantically, the explanation of ua
as completing a partial line
is sufficient. But we can also ask ourselves: Why does this definition
go through, syntactically? Because of the boundary condition
for Glue: when i = i0
, the whole thing evaluates to
A
, meaning that the left endpoint of the path is correct.
The same thing happens with the right endpoint.
The action of transporting along
ua(f)
can be described by chasing an element around the
diagram that illustrates Glue in the
case, specialising to ua
. Keep in mind that, since
the right face of the diagram βpoints in the wrong directionβ, it must
be inverted. However, the inverse of the identity equivalence is the
identity equivalence, so nothing changes (for this example).
- The action that corresponds to the left face of the diagram is to
apply the underlying function of
f
. This contributes thef .fst x
part of theuaΞ²
term below.
- For the bottom face, we have a path rather than an equivalence, so
we must
transport
along it. In this case, the path is the reflexivity onB
, but in a more generalGlue
construction, it might be a non-trivial path.
To compensate for this extra transport, we use coe1βi
, which connects
f .fst x
and
transport (Ξ» i β B) (f .fst x)
.
- Finally, we apply the inverse of the identity equivalence,
corresponding to the right face in the diagram. This immediately
computes away, and thus contributes nothing to the
uaΞ²
path.
uaΞ² : {A B : Type β} (f : A β B) (x : A) β transport (ua f) x β‘ f .fst x uaΞ² {A = A} {B} f x i = coe1βi (Ξ» _ β B) i (f .fst x)
Since ua
is a map that turns
equivalences into paths, we can compose it with a function that turns isomorphisms into equivalences to get the
map IsoβPath
.
IsoβPath : {A B : Type β} β Iso A B β A β‘ B IsoβPath (f , iiso) = ua (f , is-isoβis-equiv iiso)
Paths over uaπ
The introduction and elimination forms for Glue
can be specialised to
the case of ua
, leading to the definitions
of ua-glue
and ua-unglue
below. Their types are written in terms of interval variables and extension types, rather than using Path
s, because these typings make the
structure of Glue
more
explicit.
The first, ua-unglue
, tells us that
if we have some x : ua e i
(varying over an interval
variable i
), then we have an element of B
which agrees with e .fst x
on the left and with
x
on the right.
ua-unglue : β {A B : Type β} (e : A β B) (i : I) (x : ua e i) β B ua-unglue e i x = unattach (β i) x
We can factor the interval variable out, to get a type in terms of
PathP
, leading to an
explanation of ua-unglue
without mentioning extensions: A
path x β‘ y
over ua e
induces a path
e .fst x β‘ y
.
ua-pathpβpath : β {A B : Type β} (e : A β B) {x : A} {y : B} β PathP (Ξ» i β ua e i) x y β e .fst x β‘ y ua-pathpβpath e p i = ua-unglue e i (p i)
In the other direction, we have ua-glue
, which expresses
that a path e .fst x β‘ y
implies that x β‘ y
over ua e
. For the type of ua-glue
, suppose that we
have a partial element
defined on the left endpoint of the interval, together with an extension
of
where
is defined. What ua-glue
expresses is that we can complete this to a path in
which agrees with
and
where these are defined.
ua-glue : β {A B : Type β} (e : A β B) (i : I) (x : Partial (~ i) A) (y : B [ _ β¦ (Ξ» { (i = i0) β e .fst (x 1=1) }) ]) β ua e i ua-glue e i x y = prim^glue {Ο = i β¨ ~ i} (Ξ» { (i = i0) β x 1=1 ; (i = i1) β outS y }) (outS y)
Observe that, since
is partially in the image of
this essentially constrains
to be a βpartial preimageβ of
under the equivalence
Factoring in the type of the interval, we get the promised map between
dependent paths over ua
and paths in B.
pathβua-pathp : β {A B : Type β} (e : A β B) {x : A} {y : B} β e .fst x β‘ y β PathP (Ξ» i β ua e i) x y pathβua-pathp e {x = x} p i = ua-glue e i (Ξ» { (i = i0) β x }) (inS (p i))
The βpathp to pathβ versions of the above lemmas are definitionally
inverses, so they provide a characterisation of
PathP (ua f)
in terms of non-dependent paths.
ua-pathpβpath : β {A B : Type β} (e : A β B) {x : A} {y : B} β (e .fst x β‘ y) β (PathP (Ξ» i β ua e i) x y) ua-pathpβpath eqv .fst = pathβua-pathp eqv ua-pathpβpath eqv .snd .is-eqv y .centre = strict-fibres (ua-pathpβpath eqv) y .fst ua-pathpβpath eqv .snd .is-eqv y .paths = strict-fibres (ua-pathpβpath eqv) y .snd
The βaxiomβπ
The actual βunivalence axiomβ, as stated in the HoTT book, says that
the canonical map A β‘ B
, defined using J
, is an equivalence. This
map is idβequiv
, defined right above.
In more intuitive terms, itβs βcastingβ the identity equivalence
A β A
along a proof that A β‘ B
to get an
equivalence A β B
.
module _ where private idβequiv : {A B : Type β} β A β‘ B β A β B idβequiv {A = A} {B} = J (Ξ» x _ β A β x) (_ , id-equiv) idβequiv-refl : {A : Type β} β idβequiv (Ξ» i β A) β‘ (_ , id-equiv) idβequiv-refl {A = A} = J-refl (Ξ» x _ β A β x) (_ , id-equiv)
However, because of efficiency concerns (Agda is a
programming language, after all), instead of using idβequiv
defined using J, we
use pathβequiv
, which is defined in an auxiliary module.
pathβequiv : {A B : Type β} β A β‘ B β A β B pathβequiv p = lineβequiv (Ξ» i β p i)
Since identity of equivalences is determined by identity of their
underlying functions, to show that pathβequiv
of refl
is the identity
equivalence, we use coe1βi
to
show that transport
by refl
is the identity.
pathβequiv-refl : {A : Type β} β pathβequiv (refl {x = A}) β‘ (id , id-equiv) pathβequiv-refl {A = A} = Ξ£-path (Ξ» i x β coe1βi (Ξ» i β A) i x) (is-propβpathp (Ξ» i β is-equiv-is-prop _) _ _)
For the other direction, we must show that ua
of id-equiv
is refl
. We can do this quite
efficiently using Glue
.
Since this is a path between paths, we have two interval variables.
ua-id-equiv : {A : Type β} β ua (_ , id-equiv {A = A}) β‘ refl ua-id-equiv {A = A} i j = Glue A {Ο = i β¨ ~ j β¨ j} (Ξ» _ β A , _ , id-equiv)
We can then prove that the map pathβequiv
is an
isomorphism, hence an equivalence. Itβs very useful to have explicit
names for the proofs that pathβequiv
and ua
are equivalences without
referring to components of PathβEquiv
, so we
introduce names for them as well.
PathβEquiv : {A B : Type β} β Iso (A β‘ B) (A β B) univalence : {A B : Type β} β is-equiv (pathβequiv {A = A} {B}) univalenceβ»ΒΉ : {A B : Type β} β is-equiv (ua {A = A} {B}) PathβEquiv {A = A} {B = B} = pathβequiv , iiso where iiso : is-iso pathβequiv iiso .is-iso.inv = ua
We show that pathβequiv
inverts ua
, which means proving that
one can recover the original equivalence from the generated path.
Because of the computational nature of Cubical Agda, all we have to do
is apply uaΞ²
:
iiso .is-iso.rinv (f , is-eqv) = Ξ£-path (funext (uaΞ² (f , is-eqv))) (is-equiv-is-prop f _ _)
For the other direction, we use path
induction to reduce the problem from showing that ua
inverts pathβequiv
for an
arbitrary path (which is hard) to showing that pathβequiv
takes refl
to the identity
equivalence (pathβequiv-refl
), and that
ua
takes the identity
equivalence to refl
(ua-id-equiv
).
iiso .is-iso.linv = J (Ξ» _ p β ua (pathβequiv p) β‘ p) (ap ua pathβequiv-refl β ua-id-equiv) univalence {A = A} {B} = is-isoβis-equiv (PathβEquiv .snd) univalenceβ»ΒΉ {A = A} {B} = is-isoβis-equiv (is-iso.inverse (PathβEquiv .snd))
In some situations, it is helpful to have a proof that pathβequiv
followed by
an adjustment of levels
is
still an equivalence:
univalence-lift : {A B : Type β} β is-equiv (Ξ» e β lift (pathβequiv {A = A} {B} e)) univalence-lift {β = β} = is-isoβis-equiv morp where morp : is-iso (Ξ» e β lift {β = lsuc β} (pathβequiv e)) morp .is-iso.inv x = ua (x .lower) morp .is-iso.rinv x = lift (pathβequiv (ua (x .lower))) β‘β¨ ap lift (PathβEquiv .snd .is-iso.rinv _) β©β‘ x β morp .is-iso.linv x = PathβEquiv .snd .is-iso.linv _
Equivalence inductionπ
One useful consequence of 1 is that the type of equivalences satisfies the same induction principle as the type of identifications. By analogy with how path induction can be characterised as contractibility of singletons and transport, βequivalence inductionβ can be characterised as transport and contractibility of singletons up to equivalence:
Equiv-is-contr : β {β} (A : Type β) β is-contr (Ξ£[ B β Type β ] A β B) Equiv-is-contr A .centre = A , _ , id-equiv Equiv-is-contr A .paths (B , AβB) i = ua AβB i , p i , q i where p : PathP (Ξ» i β A β ua AβB i) id (AβB .fst) p i x = ua-glue AβB i (Ξ» { (i = i0) β x }) (inS (AβB .fst x)) q : PathP (Ξ» i β is-equiv (p i)) id-equiv (AβB .snd) q = is-propβpathp (Ξ» i β is-equiv-is-prop (p i)) _ _
Combining Equiv-is-contr
with subst
, we get an induction
principle for the type of equivalences based at
To prove
for any
it suffices to consider the case where
is
and
is the identity equivalence.
EquivJ : β {β β'} {A : Type β} β (P : (B : Type β) β A β B β Type β') β P A (_ , id-equiv) β {B : Type β} (e : A β B) β P B e EquivJ P pid eqv = subst (Ξ» e β P (e .fst) (e .snd)) (Equiv-is-contr _ .is-contr.paths (_ , eqv)) pid
Equivalence induction simplifies the proofs of many properties about
equivalences. For example, if
is an equivalence, then so is its action on paths
private is-equivβis-embedding : β {β} {A B : Type β} β (f : A β B) β is-equiv f β {x y : A} β is-equiv (ap f {x = x} {y = y}) is-equivβis-embedding f eqv = EquivJ (Ξ» B e β is-equiv (ap (e .fst))) id-equiv (f , eqv)
The proof can be rendered in English roughly as follows:
Suppose
is an equivalence
. We want to show that, for any choice of the map is an equivalence.By
induction
, it suffices to cover the case where is and is the identity function.But then, we have that is definitionally equal to which is known to be
an equivalence
.
Object classifiersπ
In category theory, the idea of classifiers (or classifying objects) often comes up when categories applied to the study of logic. For example, any elementary topos has a subobject classifier: an object such that maps corresponds to maps with propositional fibres (equivalently, inclusions In higher categorical analyses of logic, classifying objects exist for more maps: an elementary 2-topos has a discrete object classifier, which classify maps with discrete fibres.
Since a has classifiers for maps with fibres, and a has classifiers for maps with fibres, one might expect that an would have classifiers for maps with fibres that are not truncated at all. This is indeed the case! In HoTT, this fact is internalised using the univalent universes, and we can prove that univalent universes are object classifiers.
As an intermediate step, we prove that the value
of a type family
at a point
is equivalent to the fibre of
over
The proof follows from the De Morgan structure on the interval, and the
βspreadβ operation coe1βi
.
-- HoTT book lemma 4.8.1 Fibre-equiv : (B : A β Type β') (a : A) β fibre (fst {B = B}) a β B a Fibre-equiv B a = IsoβEquiv isom where isom : Iso _ _ isom .fst ((x , y) , p) = subst B p y isom .snd .inv x = (a , x) , refl isom .snd .rinv x i = coe1βi (Ξ» _ β B a) i x isom .snd .linv ((x , y) , p) i = (p (~ i) , coe1βi (Ξ» j β B (p (~ i β§ ~ j))) i y) , Ξ» j β p (~ i β¨ j)
Another fact from homotopy theory that we can import into homotopy
type theory is that any map is equivalent to a fibration. More
specifically, given a map
the total space
is equivalent to the dependent sum of the fibres. The theorems Total-equiv
and Fibre-equiv
are what
justify referring to Ξ£
the βtotal spaceβ of a
type family.
Total-equiv : (p : E β B) β E β Ξ£ B (fibre p) Total-equiv p = IsoβEquiv isom where isom : Iso _ (Ξ£ _ (fibre p)) isom .fst x = p x , x , refl isom .snd .inv (_ , x , _) = x isom .snd .rinv (b , x , q) i = q i , x , Ξ» j β q (i β§ j) isom .snd .linv x = refl
Putting these together, we get the promised theorem: The space of
maps
is equivalent to the space of fibrations with base space
and variable total space
If we allow
and
to live in different universes, then the maps are classified by the
biggest universe in which they both fit, namely
Type (β β β')
. Note that the proof of Fibration-equiv
makes
fundamental use of ua
, to construct the witnesses
that taking fibres and taking total spaces are inverses. Without ua
, we could only get an
βisomorphism-up-to-equivalenceβ of types.
Fibration-equiv : β {β β'} {B : Type β} β (Ξ£[ E β Type (β β β') ] (E β B)) β (B β Type (β β β')) Fibration-equiv {B = B} = IsoβEquiv isom where isom : Iso (Ξ£[ E β Type _ ] (E β B)) (B β Type _) isom .fst (E , p) = fibre p isom .snd .inv pβ»ΒΉ = Ξ£ _ pβ»ΒΉ , fst isom .snd .rinv prep i x = ua (Fibre-equiv prep x) i isom .snd .linv (E , p) i = ua e (~ i) , Ξ» x β fst (ua-unglue e (~ i) x) where e = Total-equiv p
To solidify the explanation that object classifiers generalise the object classifiers you would find in a we prove that any class of maps described by a property which holds of all of its fibres (or even structure on all of its fibres!) has a classifying object β the total space
For instance, if we take
to be the property of being a proposition
, this
theorem tells us that Ξ£ is-prop
classifies
subobjects. With the slight caveat that Ξ£ is-prop
is not closed under impredicative quantification, this corresponds
exactly to the notion of subobject classifier in a
since the maps with propositional fibres are precisely the injective
maps.
Since the type of βmaps into B with variable domain and P fibresβ has a very unwieldy description β both in words or in Agda syntax β we abbreviate it by The notation is meant to evoke the idea of a slice category: The objects of are objects of the category equipped with choices of maps into Similarly, the objects of are objects of the universe with a choice of map into such that holds for all the fibres of
_/[_]_ : β {β' β''} (β : Level) β (Type (β β β') β Type β'') β Type β' β Type _ _/[_]_ {β} β' P B = Ξ£ (Type (β β β')) Ξ» A β Ξ£ (A β B) Ξ» f β (x : B) β P (fibre f x)
The proof that the slice
is classified by
follows from elementary properties of
types (namely: reassociation
, distributivity
of
over
and the classification theorem Fibration-equiv
. Really,
the most complicated part of this proof is rearranging the nested sum
and product types to a form to which we can apply Fibration-equiv
.
Map-classifier : β {β β' β''} {B : Type β'} (P : Type (β β β') β Type β'') β (β /[ P ] B) β (B β Ξ£ _ P) Map-classifier {β = β} {B = B} P = (Ξ£ _ Ξ» A β Ξ£ _ Ξ» f β (x : B) β P (fibre f x)) ββ¨ Ξ£-assoc β©β (Ξ£ _ Ξ» { (x , f) β (x : B) β P (fibre f x) }) ββ¨ Ξ£-ap-fst (Fibration-equiv {β' = β}) β©β (Ξ£ _ Ξ» A β (x : B) β P (A x)) ββ¨ Ξ£-Ξ -distrib eβ»ΒΉ β©β (B β Ξ£ _ P) ββ
module ua {β} {A B : Type β} = Equiv (ua {A = A} {B} , univalenceβ»ΒΉ) unglue-is-equiv : β {β β'} {A : Type β} (Ο : I) β {B : Partial Ο (Ξ£ (Type β') (_β A))} β is-equiv {A = Glue A B} (unattach Ο) unglue-is-equiv {A = A} Ο {B = B} .is-eqv y = extendβis-contr ctr where module _ (Ο : I) (par : Partial Ο (fibre (unattach Ο) y)) where fib : .(p : IsOne Ο) β fibre (B p .snd .fst) y [ (Ο β§ Ο) β¦ (Ξ» { (Ο = i1) (Ο = i1) β par 1=1 }) ] fib p = is-contrβextend (B p .snd .snd .is-eqv y) (Ο β§ Ο) _ sys : β j β Partial (Ο β¨ Ο β¨ ~ j) A sys j (j = i0) = y sys j (Ο = i1) = outS (fib 1=1) .snd (~ j) sys j (Ο = i1) = par 1=1 .snd (~ j) ctr = inS $β attach Ο (Ξ» { (Ο = i1) β outS (fib 1=1) .fst }) (inS (hcomp (Ο β¨ Ο) sys)) , (Ξ» i β hfill (Ο β¨ Ο) (~ i) sys) ua-unglue-is-equiv : β {β} {A B : Type β} (f : A β B) β PathP (Ξ» i β is-equiv (ua-unglue f i)) (f .snd) id-equiv ua-unglue-is-equiv f = is-propβpathp (Ξ» j β is-equiv-is-prop (ua-unglue f j)) (f .snd) id-equiv uaβ : β {β} {A B C : Type β} {f : A β B} {g : B β C} β ua (f βe g) β‘ ua f β ua g uaβ {β = β} {A} {B} {C} {f} {g} = β-unique (ua (f βe g)) Ξ» i j β Glue C Ξ» where (i = i0) β ua f j , (Ξ» x β g .fst (ua-unglue f j x)) , is-propβpathp (Ξ» j β is-equiv-is-prop (Ξ» x β g .fst (ua-unglue f j x))) ((f βe g) .snd) (g .snd) j (i = i1) β ua (f βe g) j , ua-unglue (f βe g) j , ua-unglue-is-equiv (f βe g) j (j = i0) β A , f βe g (j = i1) β ua g i , ua-unglue g i , ua-unglue-is-equiv g i sym-ua : β {β} {A B : Type β} (e : A β B) β sym (ua e) β‘ ua (e eβ»ΒΉ) sym-ua {A = A} {B = B} e i j = Glue B Ξ» where (i = i0) β ua e (~ j) , ua-unglue e (~ j) , ua-unglue-is-equiv e (~ j) (i = i1) β ua (e eβ»ΒΉ) j , (Ξ» x β e .fst (ua-unglue (e eβ»ΒΉ) j x)) , is-propβpathp (Ξ» j β is-equiv-is-prop Ξ» x β e .fst (ua-unglue (e eβ»ΒΉ) j x)) (((e eβ»ΒΉ) βe e) .snd) (e .snd) j (j = i0) β B , (Ξ» x β Equiv.Ξ΅ e x (~ i)) , is-propβpathp (Ξ» j β is-equiv-is-prop Ξ» x β Equiv.Ξ΅ e x (~ j)) id-equiv (((e eβ»ΒΉ) βe e) .snd) i (j = i1) β A , e ua-inc : β {β} {Aβ Aβ : Type β} (e : Aβ β Aβ) (x : Aβ) (i : I) β ua e i ua-inc e x i = ua-glue e i (Ξ» ._ β x) (inS (e .fst x)) uaβ : β {e : Aβ β Aβ} {B : (i : I) β ua e i β Type β'} {fβ fβ} β (β a β PathP (Ξ» i β B i (ua-inc e a i)) (fβ a) (fβ (e .fst a))) β PathP (Ξ» i β (x : ua e i) β B i x) fβ fβ uaβ {e = e} {B} {fβ = fβ} {fβ} h = (Ξ» i a β comp (Ξ» j β B (i β¨ ~ j) (x' i (~ j) a)) (β i) (sys i a)) module uaβ where x' : β i j (x : ua e i) β ua e (i β¨ j) x' i j x = ua-glue e (i β¨ j) (Ξ» { (i = i0) (j = i0) β x }) (inS (unattach (β i) x)) sys : β i (a : ua e i) j β Partial (β i β¨ ~ j) (B (i β¨ ~ j) (x' i (~ j) a)) sys i a j (j = i0) = fβ (unattach (β i) a) sys i a j (i = i0) = h a (~ j) sys i a j (i = i1) = fβ a filler : β i j (a : ua e i) β B (i β¨ ~ j) (x' i (~ j) a) filler i j a = fill (Ξ» j β B (i β¨ ~ j) (x' i (~ j) a)) (β i) j (sys i a) uaβ' : β {e : Aβ β Aβ} {B : (i : I) β ua e i β Type β'} {fβ : {a : Aβ} β B i0 a} {fβ : {a : Aβ} β B i1 a} β (β a β PathP (Ξ» i β B i (ua-inc e a i)) (fβ {a}) (fβ {e .fst a})) β PathP (Ξ» i β {x : ua e i} β B i x) fβ fβ uaβ' {B = B} {fβ} {fβ} h i {x} = uaβ {B = B} {fβ = Ξ» x β fβ {x}} {fβ = Ξ» x β fβ {x}} h i x transport-β : β {β} {A B C : Type β} β (p : A β‘ B) (q : B β‘ C) (u : A) β transport (p β q) u β‘ transport q (transport p u) transport-β p q x i = transport (β-filler' p q (~ i)) (transport-filler-ext p i x) subst-β : β {β β'} {A : Type β} β (B : A β Type β') β {x y z : A} (p : x β‘ y) (q : y β‘ z) (u : B x) β subst B (p β q) u β‘ subst B q (subst B p u) subst-β B p q Bx i = transport (ap B (β-filler' p q (~ i))) (transport-filler-ext (ap B p) i Bx)
Not the fundamental theorem of engineering!β©οΈ
References
- Cohen, Cyril, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber, and Anders MΓΆrtberg. 2016. βCubical Type Theory: A Constructive Interpretation of the Univalence Axiom.β https://arxiv.org/abs/1611.02108.