module Cat.Diagram.Limit.Cone where
Limits via cones🔗
As noted in the main page on limits, most introductory material defines limits via a mathematical widget called a cone.
module _ {J : Precategory o₁ h₁} {C : Precategory o₂ h₂} (F : Functor J C) where private import Cat.Reasoning J as J import Cat.Reasoning C as C module F = Functor F record Cone : Type (o₁ ⊔ o₂ ⊔ h₁ ⊔ h₂) where no-eta-equality
A Cone
over
is given by an object (the apex
) together with a
family of maps ψ
— one for each object in
the indexing category J
— such that “everything in sight
commutes”.
field apex : C.Ob ψ : (x : J.Ob) → C.Hom apex (F.₀ x)
For every map in the indexing category, we require that the diagram below commutes. This encompasses “everything” since the only non-trivial composites that can be formed with the data at hand are of the form
commutes : ∀ {x y} (f : J.Hom x y) → F.₁ f C.∘ ψ x ≡ ψ y
These non-trivial composites consist of following the left leg of the diagram below, followed by the bottom leg. For it to commute, that path has to be the same as following the right leg.
Since paths in Hom-spaces are propositions
, to test
equality of cones, it suffices for the apices to be equal, and for their
to assign equal morphisms for every object in the shape category.
Cone-path : {x y : Cone} → (p : Cone.apex x ≡ Cone.apex y) → (∀ o → PathP (λ i → C.Hom (p i) (F.₀ o)) (Cone.ψ x o) (Cone.ψ y o)) → x ≡ y Cone-path p q i .Cone.apex = p i Cone-path p q i .Cone.ψ o = q o i Cone-path {x = x} {y} p q i .Cone.commutes {x = a} {y = b} f = is-prop→pathp (λ i → C.Hom-set _ _ (F.₁ f C.∘ q a i) (q b i)) (x .commutes f) (y .commutes f) i where open Cone
Cone maps🔗
record Cone-hom (x y : Cone) : Type (o₁ ⊔ h₂) where no-eta-equality constructor cone-hom
A Cone homomorphism
is – like
the introduction says – a map hom
in the ambient category
between the apices, such that “everything in sight commutes
”. Specifically,
for any choice of object
in the index category, the composition of hom
with the domain cone’s
ψ
(at that
object) must be equal to the codomain’s ψ
.
field hom : C.Hom (Cone.apex x) (Cone.apex y) commutes : ∀ o → Cone.ψ y o C.∘ hom ≡ Cone.ψ x o
private unquoteDecl eqv = declare-record-iso eqv (quote Cone-hom) Cone-hom-path : ∀ {x y} {f g : Cone-hom x y} → Cone-hom.hom f ≡ Cone-hom.hom g → f ≡ g Cone-hom-path p i .Cone-hom.hom = p i Cone-hom-path {x = x} {y} {f} {g} p i .Cone-hom.commutes o j = is-set→squarep (λ i j → C.Hom-set _ _) (λ j → Cone.ψ y o C.∘ p j) (f .Cone-hom.commutes o) (g .Cone-hom.commutes o) refl i j
Since cone homomorphisms are morphisms in the underlying category
with extra properties, we can lift the laws from the underlying category
to the category of Cones
. The definition of
compose
is
the enlightening part, since we have to prove that two cone
homomorphisms again preserve all the commutativities.
Cones : Precategory _ _ Cones = cat where open Precategory compose : {x y z : _} → Cone-hom y z → Cone-hom x y → Cone-hom x z compose {x} {y} {z} F G = r where open Cone-hom r : Cone-hom x z r .hom = hom F C.∘ hom G r .commutes o = Cone.ψ z o C.∘ hom F C.∘ hom G ≡⟨ C.pulll (commutes F o) ⟩≡ Cone.ψ y o C.∘ hom G ≡⟨ commutes G o ⟩≡ Cone.ψ x o ∎ cat : Precategory _ _ cat .Ob = Cone cat .Hom = Cone-hom cat .id = record { hom = C.id ; commutes = λ _ → C.idr _ } cat ._∘_ = compose cat .idr f = Cone-hom-path (C.idr _) cat .idl f = Cone-hom-path (C.idl _) cat .assoc f g h = Cone-hom-path (C.assoc _ _ _)
Terminal cones as limits🔗
Note that cones over some diagram contain the exact same data as natural transformations from a constant functor to To obtain a limit, all we need is a way of stating that a given cone is universal. In particular, the terminal object in the category of cones over a diagram (if it exists!) is the limit of
The proof here is just shuffling data around: this is not totally surprising, as both constructions contain the same data, just organized differently.
Cone→cone : (K : Cone) → Const (Cone.apex K) => F Cone→cone K .η = K .Cone.ψ Cone→cone K .is-natural x y f = C.idr _ ∙ sym (K .Cone.commutes f) is-terminal-cone→is-limit : ∀ {K : Cone} → is-terminal Cones K → is-limit F (Cone.apex K) (Cone→cone K) is-terminal-cone→is-limit {K = K} term = isl where open Cone-hom open is-ran open Cone isl : is-ran _ F _ (Cone→cone K) isl .σ {M = M} α = nt where α' : Cone α' .apex = M .Functor.F₀ tt α' .ψ x = α .η x α' .commutes f = sym (α .is-natural _ _ f) ∙ C.elimr (M .Functor.F-id) nt : M => !Const (K .apex) nt .η x = term α' .centre .hom nt .is-natural tt tt tt = C.elimr (M .Functor.F-id) ∙ C.introl refl isl .σ-comm = ext λ x → term _ .centre .commutes _ isl .σ-uniq {σ' = σ'} x = ext λ _ → ap hom $ term _ .paths λ where .hom → σ' .η _ .commutes _ → sym (x ηₚ _)
The inverse direction of this equivalence also consists of packing and unpacking data.
is-limit→is-terminal-cone : ∀ {x} {eps : Const x => F} → (L : is-limit F x eps) → is-terminal Cones (record { commutes = is-limit.commutes L }) is-limit→is-terminal-cone {x = x} L K = term where module L = is-limit L module K = Cone K open Cone-hom term : is-contr (Cone-hom K _) term .centre .hom = L.universal K.ψ K.commutes term .centre .commutes _ = L.factors K.ψ K.commutes term .paths f = Cone-hom-path (sym (L.unique K.ψ K.commutes (f .hom) (f .commutes)))
open Ran Terminal-cone→Limit : Terminal Cones → Limit F Terminal-cone→Limit x .Ext = _ Terminal-cone→Limit x .eps = _ Terminal-cone→Limit x .has-ran = is-terminal-cone→is-limit (x .Terminal.has⊤) Limit→Terminal-cone : Limit F → Terminal Cones Limit→Terminal-cone x .Terminal.top = _ Limit→Terminal-cone x .Terminal.has⊤ = is-limit→is-terminal-cone (Limit.has-limit x)